VI. THE TEACHER'S USE OF THE IMAGINATION


magination is governed by the same general laws of association which

control habit and memory. n these two former topics the emphasis was

upon getting a desired result without any attention to the form of that

result. magination, on the other hand, has to do with the way past

experience is used and the form taken by the result. t merges into

memory in one direction and into thinking in another. No one definition

has be
n found acceptable--in fact, in no field of psychology is there

more difference of opinion, in no topic are terms used more loosely,

than in this one of imagination. Stated in very general terms,

imagination is the process of reproducing, or reconstructing any form of

experience. The result of such a process is a mental image. When the

fact that it is reproduction or reconstruction is lost sight of, and the

image reacted to as if it were present, an illusion or hallucination

results.



mages may be classified according to the sense through which the

original experience came, into visual, auditory, gustatory, tactile,

kinaesthetic, and so on. n many discussions of imagery the term

"picture" has been used to describe it, and hence in the thought of many

it is limited rather definitely to the visual field. Of course this is

entirely wrong. The recall of a melody, or of the touch of velvet, or of

the fragrance of a rose, is just as much mental imagery as the recall of

the sight of a friend.



Three points of dispute in connection with image types are worth while

noting. First, the question is raised by some psychologists as to

whether kinaesthetic or motor images really exist. An example of such an

image would be to imagine yourself as dancing, or walking downstairs, or

writing your name, or saying the word "bubble." Those who object to such

an image type claim that when one tries to get such an image, the

attempt initiates slight muscle movements and the result is a sense

experience instead of an imaged one. They believe this always happens

and that therefore a motor image is an impossibility. Others agree that

this reinstatement of actual movements often happens, but contend that

in such cases the image precedes the movement and that the resulting

movement does not always take place. The question is still in dispute.



The second question in dispute is as to the possibility of classifying

people according to the predominant type of their imagery. People used

to be classed as "visualizers," "audiles." etc., the supposition being

that their mental imagery was predominantly in terms of vision or

hearing. This is being seriously questioned, and experimental work seems

to show that such a classification, at least with the majority of

people, is impossible. The results which are believed to warrant such a

conclusion are as follows: First, no one has ever been tested who always

used one type of image. Second, the type of image used changed with the

following factors: the material, the purpose of the subject, the

familiarity of the subject with the experience imagined. For example,

the same person would, perhaps, visualize if he were imaging landscape,

but get an auditory image of a friend's voice instead of a visual image

of him. He might, when under experimental conditions with the

controlling purpose,--that of examining his images,--get visual images,

but, when under ordinary conditions, get a larger number of auditory and

kinaesthetic images. He might when thought was flowing smoothly be using

auditory and motor images, but upon the appearance of some obstacle or

difficulty in the process find himself flooded with visual images.

Third, subjects who ranked high in one type of imagery ranked high in

others, and subjects who ranked low in one type ranked low also in

others. The ability seems to be that of getting clear image types, or

the lack of it, rather than the ability to get one type. Fourth, most of

the subjects reported that the first image was usually followed by

others of different types. The conclusions then, that individuals,

children as well as adults, are rarely of one fixed type, the mixed type

being the usual one, is being generally accepted. n fact, it seems much

more probable that materials and outside conditions can more easily be

classified as usually arousing a certain type of image, than people can

be classified into types.



The third point of controversy grows out of the second. Some

psychologists are asking what is the value of such a classification?

Suppose people could be put under types in imagery, what would be the

practical advantage? Such an attempt at classification is futile and not

worth while, for two reasons. First, the result of the mental

processes--the goal arrived at is the important thing, and the

particular type of image used is of little importance. Does it make any

difference to the business man whether his clerk thinks in terms of the

visual images of words or in terms of motor images so long as he sells

the goods? To the teacher of geography, does it make any difference

whether John in his thinking of the value of trees is seeing them in his

mind's eye, or hearing the wind rustle through the leaves, or smelling

the moist earth, leaf-mold, or having none of these images, if he gets

the meaning, and reaches a right conclusion? Second, the sense which

gives the clearest, most dependable impressions is not the one

necessarily in terms of which the experience is recalled. One of the

chief values urged for a classification according to image type of

people, especially children, has been that the appeal could then be made

through the corresponding sense organs. For instance, Group A, being

visualizers, will be asked to read the material silently; Group B,

audiles, will have the material read to them; Group C, motiles, will be

asked to read the material orally, or asked to dramatize it. For each

group the major appeal should be made in terms of the sense

corresponding to their image type. But such a correspondence as this

does not exist. An individual may learn best by use of his eyes and yet

very seldom use visual images in recall. This is true of most people in

reading. Most people grasp the meaning of a passage better when they

read it than when they hear it read, and yet the predominant type of

word image is auditory-motor. Hence if any classification of children is

attempted it should be according to the sense by means of which they

learn best, and not according to some supposed image type. Many methods

of appeal for all children is the safest practical suggestion.



mages may also be classified according to the use made of past

experience. Past experience may be recalled in approximately the same

form in which it occurred, or it may be reconstructed. n the former

case the image is called reproductive image or memory image; in the

latter form it is called productive or creative image, or image of the

imagination. The reproductive image never duplicates experience, but in

its major features it closely corresponds to it, whereas the productive

image breaks up old experiences and from them makes new wholes which

correspond to no definite occurrence. The elements found in both kinds

of imagery must come from experience. One cannot imagine anything the

elements of which he has not experienced. Creative imagination

transcends experience only in the sense that it remodels and remakes,

but the result of that activity produces new wholes as far removed from

the actual occurrences as "Alice in Wonderland" is from the humdrum life

of a tenement dweller. Just the same, the fact that the elements used in

creative work must be drawn from experience is extremely suggestive from

a practical point of view. t demonstrates the need of a rich sensory

life for every child. t also explains the reason for the lack of

appreciation on the part of immature children of certain types of

literature and certain moral questions.



No more need be said here of the reproductive image, as it is synonymous

with the memory image and was therefore treated fully under the topic of

memory. One fact should be borne in mind, however, and that is, that the

creative image is to some extent dependent on the reproductive image as

it involves recall. However, as productive imagery involves the recall

of elements or parts rather than wholes, an individual may have talent

in creative imagery without being above the average in exact

reproduction.



Productive imagery may be classified as fanciful, realistic, and

idealistic according to the character of the material used. Fanciful

productive imagery is characterized by its spontaneity, its disregard of

the probable and possible, its vividness of detail. t is its own

reward, and does not look to any result beyond itself. Little children's

imaginations are of this type--it is their play world of make-believe.

The incongruity and absurdity of their images have been compared to the

dreams of adults. Lacking in experience, without knowledge of natural

laws, their imagination runs riot with the materials it has at its

command. Some adults still retain it to a high degree--witness the myths

and fairy stories, "Alice in Wonderland," and the like. All adults in

their "castle-building" indulge in this type of imagery to some extent.

Realistic productive imagery, as its name implies, adheres more strictly

to actual conditions, it deals with the probable. t usually is

constructed for a purpose, being put to some end beyond itself. t lacks

much of the emotional element possessed by the other two types. This is

the kind most valuable in reasoning and thinking. t deals with new

situations--constructs them, creates means of dealing with them, and

forecasts the results. t is the type of productive imagery called into

play by inventors, by craftsmen, by physicians, by teachers--in fact, by

any one who tries to bring about a change in conditions by the

functioning of a definite thought process. This is the kind of imagery

which most interests grammar school pupils. They demand facts, not

fancies. They are most active in making changes in a world of things.



dealistic productive imagery does not fly in the face of reality as

does the fanciful, nor does it adhere so strictly to facts as does the

realistic. t deals with the possible--with what may be, but with what

is not yet. t always looks to the future, for if realized it is no

longer idealistic. t is enjoyed for its own sake but does not exist for

that alone, but looks towards some result. t is concerned primarily

with human lives and has a strong emotional tone. t is the heart of

ideals. The adolescent revels in this type of productive imagery. His

dreams concerning his own future, his service to his fellow men, his

success, and the like involve much idealistic imagery. Hero worship

involves it. t is one of the differences between the man with "vision"

and the man without.



The importance of productive imagery cannot be overemphasized. This

power to create the new out of the old is one of the greatest

possessions of mankind. All progress in every field, whether individual

or racial, depends upon it. From the fertility and richness of man's

productive imagination must come all the suggestions which will make

this world other than what it is. Therefore one of the greatest tasks of

education at present is to cherish and cultivate this power. One cannot

fail to recognize, however, that with the emphasis at present so largely

upon memory, the cultivation of the imagination is being pushed into the

background despite all our theories to the contrary. Not only is

productive imagery as a whole worth while, but each type is valuable. An

adult lacking power of fanciful imagination lacks power to enjoy certain

elements in life and lacks a very definite means of recreation. Lacking

in realistic imagination he is unable to deal successfully with new

situations, but must forever remain in bondage to the past. Without

idealistic imagination he lacks the motive which makes men strive to be

better, more efficient--other than what they are. At certain times in

child development one type may need special encouragement, and at

another time some other. All should, however, be borne in mind and

developed along right and wholesome lines; otherwise, left to itself,

any one of these, and especially the last, may be a source of danger to

the character.



mages may be classified according to the material dealt with into

object images or concrete images and into word or abstract images. No

one of these terms is very good as a name of the image referred to. The

first group--object or concrete image--refers to an image in which the

sensory qualities, such as color, size, rhythm, sweetness, harmony,

etc., are present. The images of a friend, of a text-book, of the

national anthem, of an orange, of the schoolroom, and so on, would all

be object images. A word or abstract image is one which is a symbol. t

stands for and represents certain sensory experiences, the quality of

which does not appear in the image. Any word, number, mathematical or

chemical symbol--in fact, any abstract symbol will come under this type

of image. f in the first list of illustrations, instead of having

images of the real objects, an individual had images of words in each

case, the images would be abstract or verbal images. Abstract images

shade into concrete by gradual degrees--there is no sharp line of

division between the two; however, they do form two different kinds of

images, two forms which may have the same meaning.



The question as to the respective use and value of these two kinds of

images is given different answers. There is no question but that the

verbal image is more economical than the object image. t saves energy

and time. t brings with it less of irrelevant detail and is more stable

than the object image, and therefore results in more accurate thinking.

t is abstract in nature and therefore has more general application. On

the other hand, it has been claimed for the object image that it

necessarily precedes the verbal image--is fundamental to it; that it is

essential in creative work dealing with materials and sounds and in the

appreciation of certain types of descriptive literature, and that in any

part of the thinking process when, because of difficulty of some kind, a

percept would help, an object image would be of the same assistance. t

is concerning these supposed advantages of the object image that there

has been most dispute. There is no proof that the line of growth is

necessarily from percept, through object image, to verbal image. n

certain fields, notably smell, the object image is almost absent and yet

the verbal images in that field carry meaning. t is also true that

people whose power of getting clear-cut, vivid object images is almost

nil seem to be in nowise hampered by that fact in their use of the

symbols. Knowing the unreliability of the object image, it would seem

very unsafe to use it as the link between percept and symbol. Much

better to connect the symbol directly with the experience and let it

gain its meaning from that. As to its value in constructive work in

arts, literature, drama, and invention, the testimony of some experts in

each field bears witness that it is not a necessary accompaniment of

success. The musician need not hear, mentally, all the harmonies,

changes, intervals; he may think them in terms of notes, rests, etc., as

he composes. The poet need not see the scene he is describing; verbal

images may bear his meanings. Of course this does not mean that object

images may not be present too, but the point is that the worker is not

dependent on them. The aid offered by object images in time of

difficulty is still more open to doubt. As an illustration of what is

meant by this: Suppose a child to be given a carpeting example in

arithmetic which he finds himself unable to solve. The claim is made

that if he will then call up a concrete image of the room, he will see

that the carpet is laid in strips and that suggestion may set him right.

But it has been proved experimentally over and over again that if he

doesn't know that carpets are laid that way, he will never get it from

the image, and if he does know it, he doesn't need an object image. t

seems to be a fact that object images do not function, in the sense that

one cannot get a correct answer as to color, or form, or number from

them. One can read off from a concrete image what he knows to be true of

it--or else it is just guessing. "Knowing" in each case involves

observation and judgment, and that means verbal images. Students whose

power of concrete imagery is low do, on the average, in situations where

a concrete image would supposedly help, just as well as students whose

power in this field is high. t does seem to be true that object images

give a vividness and color to mental life which may result in a keener

appreciation of certain types of literature. This warmth and vividness

which object images add to the mental processes of those who have them

is a boon.



On the whole, then, word images are the more valuable of the two types.

Upon them depends, primarily, the ability to handle new situations, and

even in the constructive fields they are all sufficient. These two

facts, added to the fact that they are more accurate, speedy, and

general in application, makes them a necessary part of the mental

equipment of an efficient worker, and means that much more attention

must be given to the development of productive symbol images.



Two warnings should be borne in mind: First, although the object images

are not necessary in general, as discussed above, to any given

individual, because of his particular habits of thought, they may be

necessary accompaniments to his mental processes. Second, although

object images may not help in giving understanding or appreciation under

new conditions, still the method of asking students to try to image

certain conditions is worth while because it makes them stop and think,

which is always a help. Whether they get object or word images in the

process makes no difference.



The discussion concerning the possibility of "imageless" thought, while

an interesting one, cannot be entered into here. Whether "meanings" can

exist in the human mind apart from any carrier in the form of some

sensory or imaginal state is unsettled, but the discussion has drawn

attention to at least the very fragmentary nature of those carriers. A

few fragments of words, a mental shrug of the shoulder, a feeling of the

direction in which a certain course is leading, a consciousness of one's

attitude towards a plan or person--and the conclusion is reached. The

thinking, or it may even have been reasoning, involved few clear-cut

images of any kind. The fragmentary, schematic nature of the carriers

and the large part played by feelings of direction and attitude are the

rather astonishing results of the introspective analysis resulting from

this discussion. This sort of thinking is valuable for the same reasons

that thinking in terms of words is valuable--it only goes a step

further, but it needs direction and training.



mages of all kinds have been discussed as if they stood out clearly

differentiated from all other types of mental states. This is necessary

in order that their peculiar characteristics and functions may be clear.

However, they are not so clearly defined in actual mental life, but

shade into each other and into other mental states, giving rise to

confusion and error. The two greatest sources of error are: first, the

confusion of image with percept, and second, the confusion of memory

image with image of the imagination. The chief difference between these

mental states as they exist is a difference in kind and amount of

associations. These different associates usually give to the percept a

vividness and material reality which the other two lack. They give to

the memory image a feeling of pastness and trueness which the image of

imagination lacks. Therefore lack of certain associations, due to lack

of experience or knowledge, or presence of associations due to these

same causes and to the undue vividness of other connections, could

easily result in one of these states being mistaken for another. There

is no inherent difference between them. The first type of confusion,

between percept and image, has been recently made the subject of

investigation. Perky found that even with trained adults, if the

perceptual stimulus was slight, it was mistaken for an image. All

illusions would come under this head. Children's imaginary companions,

when really believed in, are explained by this confusion. However, the

confusion is much more general than these illustrations would seem to

imply. The fact that "Love is blind," that "We see what we look for" are

but statements of this same confusion, and these two facts enter into

multitudes of situations all through life. The need to "see life clearly

and see it whole" is an imperative one.



The second type of confusion, between reproductive and productive

memory, is even more common. The "white lies" of children, the

embroidering of a story by the adult, the adding to and adding to the

original experience until all sense of what really happened is lost, are

but ordinary facts of everyday experiences. The unreliability of witness

and testimony is due, in part, to this confusion.





QUESTONS





1. How is the process of imagination like memory?



2. What is the relation of imagination to thinking?



3. What kind of images do you seek to have children use in their work in

the subjects which you teach?



4. Can you classify the members of your class as visualizers, audiles,

and the like?



5. f one learns most readily by reading rather than hearing, does it

follow that his images will be largely visual? Why?



6. Give examples from your own experience of memory images; of creative

images.



7. To what degree does creative imagination depend upon past

experiences?



8. What type of imagery is most important for the work of the inventor?

The farmer? The social reformer?



9. Of what significance in the life of an adult is fanciful imagery?



10. What, if any, is the danger involved in reveling in idealistic

productive imagery?



11. What advantages do verbal images possess as over against object

images?



12. Why would you ask children to try to image in teaching literature,

geography, history, or any other subject for which you are responsible?



13. How would you handle a boy who is hi the habit of confusing memory

images with images of imagination?



14. n what sense is it true that all progress, is dependent upon

productive imagination?



* * * * *



More

;